Examples 1-4 are (I think) examples of conspiracy (where we are attribute each conspirators actions to the others) 5-6 are examples of procurement (causing another to act in a way that you intend them to do, so that their actions are attributed to you).
7 is Rankin's garage (shorn of that cases distractions of illegality and children) which I think the same as Childs v Desmeroux. Here the defendant has only facilitated the wrong suffered.
Now, maybe the law should attribute the wrong to the party who has (merely) facilitated it. I don't think I have a proof that we should not. But the law hitherto has not gone that far, it also seems a rational place to stop, and so Rankin's and Childs v D (and
all the cases for no liability cited by Christine B, where D had been negligent and that had foreseeably injured P) look defensible.
Not easy though. Not even I claimed that. But as presently advised, I'm biting the bullet and controversially claiming the SCC got it right.
From: Benjamin Zipursky
Sent: Wednesday, 16 May, 16:04
Subject: Re: ODG: Rankin's Garage
To: Robert Stevens
Cc: obligations@uwo.ca, Jason W Neyers
Rob's confidence and clarity about moral/legal divisions (and individuation of legal wrongs) is inspiring (not being sarcastic), and sometimes infectious. Not so for me in this case, I am afraid. Largely for the reasons Jason and Allan articulated, Rankin as
written is unpersuasive; the assertion of unforeseeability is simply not credible. And, like Allan, I think it is actually quite a difficult case. I do not rule out that the Court might have gotten it right or that it might have gotten it wrong.
My big problem with Rob's comment is that -- although I would like to see this categorically -- I am afraid that I am not clear which category would really work.
The following (doubtless overextended) series of hypotheticals illustrates my problem.
1. Person X plans with persons Y that Y will select some member of racial group R and shoot that person causing serious injury. X's contribution, beyond the plan, is leaving a loaded handgun in an small box in X's large mailbox by the street. Y follows
through and V1 is injured. Presumably X faces liability in tort law, not just criminal law, as a joint tortfeasor in the battery.
2. Same as 1, but the plan is that Y will run down V2, using X's car, and X has left his car keys in the glove compartment, for Y to use it, which he does.
3. Same as 2, but X and Y plan that they will do it on the 7th day of each month, always in a different neighborhood, with a code as to where the car will be. V3, and many others, are injured.
4. Same as 3, but X has a religious conversion and abandons his plan and communicates this to Y in several different emails. Nonetheless,Y never gets the message because X has negligently sent those emails to the wrong email address. X also negligently leaves
his keys in the car one day, which happens to be 7th of the month. Y runs down V4, seriously injuring him.
5. A city experiences a spate of intentional running downs of people of race R -- several per month (and 50 per year). The drivers are part of a gang, Y, that always chooses a car on the street in which the keys have been left in the car. The city is very
open about this spate, publicizing it greatly, but it has not caught the perpetrators. X does not know any members of Y, but he hates members of group R. He deliberately parks his car on the street near where many of these running-downs have occurred, leaving
the keys in it, and a member of Y severely injures V5 using X's car.
6. Same as 5, but gang Y is not selective about who they run down, and X is not selective either -- he just likes random injuries and so deliberately leaves his keys in his car, hoping that it will be used in this manner. A member of Y uses X's car to injury
V6.
7. Same as 5, but X has no animus, racial or otherwise. He negligently leaves his keys in the car in a high-runnning-down neighborhood, and a member of Y uses X's car and injures V7.
8. A different city, C2, has a much less severe version of the same problem -- 10 times per year, not 50 times per year. Yet everyone in the city is made known of the problem. Otherwise same as 6; X deliberately leaves his keys in the car, hoping it will
be used to injure someone. X's car is used by a member of Y and V8 is severely injured.
9. Same as 8, but X has no animus, racial or otherwise. He negligently leaves his keys in the car in a neighborhood where many of these events occurred, and a member of Y uses X's car and injures V9.
10. Same as 6, but gang Y is not interested in injuring people at all, just interested in drugs and booze and fast driving and theft. Members of Y nonetheless find cars with keys left in them and go joyriding, and seriously injure 50 persons per year in the
city. X likes serious injuries, so he deliberately leaves his keys in the car in neighborhood where this has frequently occurred. A member of Y uses X's car and causes serious injury to V10.
11. Same as 10, but X negligently eaves his keys in the car in a neighborhood where this has frequently happened (and is known to have frequently happened). A member of Y uses X's car and causes serious injury to V11.
12. Same as 11, but in C2 (see 8, above -- in City 2, this occurs only 10 times per year, not 50 times per year). X negligently leaves his keys in the car in one of the neighborhoods where this has most frequently occurred. A member of Y uses X's
car and causes serious injury to V12.
13. Rankin
The question is, assuming that Rob would think that V1 has a tort claim against X, where should one draw the line before 13 (Rankin)? Note that 4, 7, 9, 11, and 12 all involve negligence by X in leaving keys in the car. I concede that 4 is tricky,
but the big question to me is whether Rob is willing to say that V7 (see 7) has no negligence claim against X. If not -- if one concedes V7 has a claim there -- then I think we are out of the level of the categorical. If one is is willing to bite the bullet
and say that V7 has no claim, why? I am inclined to think that Heaven, Donoghue, MacPherson, and Palsgraf tend to cut in the other direction on V7 (that is basically where Ernie came out in his response to this case). But I am
open to hearing why this is wrong.
Best,
Ben Zipursky
"Why isn’t there also another wrong of leaving a car in an unsecured and, in the circumstances, dangerous condition (dangerous in the sense that leaving a gun on my front lawn would be dangerous)?"
That is certainly bad behaviour, worthy of criticism, but it isn't a civil wrong to the plaintiff.
There are cases where a claimant suffers multiple wrongs from one event. So, if I bail my goods to you, and a thief steals them, when if you'd been careful they would not have been, I've suffered two wrongs. The thief stole my things, and you broke your assumed
duty to me to take care of them.
Looking at Rankin's Garage from the perspective of the plaintiff, I count one wrong, not two or three. The issue then becomes "whose doing was that." We have rules of attribution for settling that.
If our questions are has the defendant behaved in a morally blameworthy way, and is he in some way morally responsible for the njuries the plaintiff suffered? my answers are yes. I'm not sure that ought to be enough.
Sent: Wednesday, May 16, 2018 11:56:37 AM
Subject: ODG: Rankin's Garage
On behalf of Allan Beever:
Dear all
Some overly long thoughts surrounding this case.
I would like to be able to support Rob’s approach, as it would settle things neatly, but I don’t think that I can. He says:
Here the wrong was being negligently injured by another's careless driving. Q: Who did that? A: The driver of the vehicle.
Unfortunately, I think that this begs the question. Certainly, Rob has identified
a wrong, but why is this the wrong, ie the only wrong? Why isn’t there also another wrong of leaving a car in an unsecured and, in the circumstances, dangerous condition (dangerous in the sense that leaving a gun on my front lawn would be dangerous)?
In general, I think that we (or most of us) have a very strong cultural bias (I say cultural, but if someone tells me that there is also a biological basis for it, I’d be happy to accept) in favour of thinking that there are single culprits for wrongs – even
single causes of events (that has to be biological I guess) – but there is really no justification for thinking this way. In this case, we might think that C was the most serious wrongdoer – the
wrongdoer, if you like – but that in itself says nothing – literally nothing – about whether R was also a wrongdoer.
And as Rob quite rightly says, this kind of thinking is inconsistent with Dorset Yacht. Weren’t the borstal boys “the” wrongdoers in that case? Let me cheat a little:
[I]t is said that [J] must fail because there is a general principle that no person can be responsible for the acts of another who is not his servant or acting on his behalf. But here the ground of liability is not responsibility for the acts of the [driver,
C]: it is liability for damage caused by the carelessness of these [employees of R] that their carelessness would probably result in [joyriders] causing damage of this kind. So the question is really one of remoteness of damage.
(Of course, much here might depend on what you take ‘probably’ to mean.)
If we put the law entirely aside, it would seem to me quite wrong to say that R in this case bore no moral responsibility whatsoever for the events that occurred. Of course, I am not saying that R was as to blame as J or C were, or even as C’s mother was.
It may help to think of it this way. In the light of these events, I would certainly hope that in future R would make sure that keys were not left in cars again. If R didn’t take this precaution, then I would think that that would be wrong. But if I think that,
then if I also think that these events were at the time a reasonably foreseeable consequence of R’s leaving the keys in the car etc, then aren’t I compelled to come to the same conclusion: that R was to some extent in the wrong?
That brings me to another point. Don’t the majority in this case find for R on the ground that the events were unforeseeable? Don’t they say that, though it may have been foreseeable that an adult would have stolen the car it would not be foreseeable, or there
wasn’t sufficient evidence to conclude that it was foreseeable, that a minor would steal the car? And that a minor would take the car for a joyride? Isn’t this odd? As Jason says, this seems rather otherworldly. Kids do this all the time. It is one of the
significant problems of modern policing. It seems that this was even more true of the area in which these events took place. Can we agree that, even if we approve of the result in the case, we cannot accept the reasoning of the majority? Perhaps I am being
unfair, but it seems to me that the majority have either lost touch with a reality of modern life or are just not telling the truth. I suspect the latter. Should we really be comfortable with this, as long as we get the result we are after?
Another thing: I am struck by the fact that at least many of the Canadian contributors to this discussion have argued along the following lines. “The law in Canada says x, y and z. According to x, y and z, the result should have been r. The majority got to
not-r by doing something illegitimate.” Some commentators, I am thinking especially of Lewis, have even disclaimed any personal commitment to r. They just think that r is what the law in Canada requires. Am I being unfair when I say that one line of response
to this has been to say something that could be paraphrased as “Well who cares about that? Just get the right result.” I don’t detect much legal analysis in these replies (I assume that citation of case law, especially the case law of a foreign jurisdiction,
is not itself legal analysis). But isn’t this something that we should care about?
It might also be worth while to identify precisely why you think that J should not be able to recover (if that is what you do think). Is it because J broke the law in stealing the car. If so, then isn’t this intuition best reflected in the illegality defence
rather than in the way that it was reflected in this case? Shouldn’t we then say that the majority were wrong, though they got right result rather than just siding with them? My own view is that this “J is an outlaw” response to the case is likely to explain
much of the antipathy to J recovering, but for reasons I won’t repeat here my view is that this position is unjustified. Perhaps the intuition, though, is that J should not be able to sue R when J consciously took the risk that materialised in his injury.
This is to say that J was volens – that R created a risk but that J voluntarily ‘took on’ that same risk when deciding to steal a car from R. Whether you think that will depend on what you make of his age, etc. Again, though, this doesn’t really support the
majority. Perhaps you think that C (or J himself) was so much more responsible for J’s injury than R was that R should not have to pay damages at all; in which case in principle this could be reflected properly in the contribution (or contributory negligence)
rules, at least if they (as I see it) were approached more rationally than they are at present. Again, this is not the majority’s view. If you are against J here for a different reason, I’d be interested to hear what it might be.
And one last thing: It might be worth reflecting on the kind of disagreement that we are seeing here. We have distinguished commentators on the law unable to agree on pretty basic questions such as whether this was an entirely ordinary kind of case or whether
it raised exceptional issues. Some say that finding liability would involve an outrageous extension of the law of negligence. Others say (including the dissenters) that it would involve no extension at all. My own view is that the cases that impose rules that
restrict recover are (to my mind) pretty clearly cutting back on liability rather than failing to extend it. Some think that there should be liability in this case. Others that it is ‘obvious’ that there should not; that this is even a simple and clear case
in which anyone could see that there should be no liability. No doubt about it.
My question is: What are we actually arguing about here? Anything at all? If scholars who have dedicated themselves to the study of this area of the law can be so divided on these really rather basic questions, perhaps we have to admit that – at least if we
are talking about today’s positive law of negligence – the law has become so empty that almost anything can be said about it. If the law’s job is to guide practical reason, then this area of the law seems to be on strike.
Just to clarify, I am not saying that the moral question raised in the case was an easy one. I would say that it is a difficult one as it tests the boundaries of our conceptions of responsibility, but that matter is separate. It might be worth reflecting on
the fact that here in NZ (and I imagine elsewhere), there is considerable controversy over high speed police chases that end in kids who have stolen cars being killed. One response to this kind of think is to say “Well, it’s the bloody kids’ fault. Shouldn’t
have stolen the car”. I have to say that I am proud not to belong to that class of thinker. It is also notable that that isn’t the police’s view. They clearly think that they do have an obligation to care for the safety of the joyrider. Quite right too. Also,
there are of course other ways of looking at tort law than focusing on today’s positive ‘law’, but that is another matter too.
All the best
Allan
Jason Neyers
Professor of Law
Faculty of Law
Western University
Law Building Rm 26
t. 519.661.2111 (x88435)
"Why isn’t there also another wrong of leaving a car in an unsecured and, in the circumstances, dangerous condition (dangerous in the sense that leaving a gun on my front lawn would be dangerous)?"
That is certainly bad behaviour, worthy of criticism, but it isn't a civil wrong to the plaintiff.
There are cases where a claimant suffers multiple wrongs from one event. So, if I bail my goods to you, and a thief steals them, when if you'd been careful they would not have been, I've suffered two wrongs. The thief stole my things, and you broke your assumed
duty to me to take care of them.
Looking at Rankin's Garage from the perspective of the plaintiff, I count one wrong, not two or three. The issue then becomes "whose doing was that." We have rules of attribution for settling that.
If our questions are has the defendant behaved in a morally blameworthy way, and is he in some way morally responsible for the njuries the plaintiff suffered? my answers are yes. I'm not sure that ought to be enough.
Sent: Wednesday, May 16, 2018 11:56:37 AM
Subject: ODG: Rankin's Garage
On behalf of Allan Beever:
Dear all
Some overly long thoughts surrounding this case.
I would like to be able to support Rob’s approach, as it would settle things neatly, but I don’t think that I can. He says:
Here the wrong was being negligently injured by another's careless driving. Q: Who did that? A: The driver of the vehicle.
Unfortunately, I think that this begs the question. Certainly, Rob has identified
a wrong, but why is this the wrong, ie the only wrong? Why isn’t there also another wrong of leaving a car in an unsecured and, in the circumstances, dangerous condition (dangerous in the sense that leaving a gun on my front lawn would be dangerous)?
In general, I think that we (or most of us) have a very strong cultural bias (I say cultural, but if someone tells me that there is also a biological basis for it, I’d be happy to accept) in favour of thinking that there are single culprits for wrongs – even
single causes of events (that has to be biological I guess) – but there is really no justification for thinking this way. In this case, we might think that C was the most serious wrongdoer – the
wrongdoer, if you like – but that in itself says nothing – literally nothing – about whether R was also a wrongdoer.
And as Rob quite rightly says, this kind of thinking is inconsistent with Dorset Yacht. Weren’t the borstal boys “the” wrongdoers in that case? Let me cheat a little:
[I]t is said that [J] must fail because there is a general principle that no person can be responsible for the acts of another who is not his servant or acting on his behalf. But here the ground of liability is not responsibility for the acts of the [driver,
C]: it is liability for damage caused by the carelessness of these [employees of R] that their carelessness would probably result in [joyriders] causing damage of this kind. So the question is really one of remoteness of damage.
(Of course, much here might depend on what you take ‘probably’ to mean.)
If we put the law entirely aside, it would seem to me quite wrong to say that R in this case bore no moral responsibility whatsoever for the events that occurred. Of course, I am not saying that R was as to blame as J or C were, or even as C’s mother was.
It may help to think of it this way. In the light of these events, I would certainly hope that in future R would make sure that keys were not left in cars again. If R didn’t take this precaution, then I would think that that would be wrong. But if I think that,
then if I also think that these events were at the time a reasonably foreseeable consequence of R’s leaving the keys in the car etc, then aren’t I compelled to come to the same conclusion: that R was to some extent in the wrong?
That brings me to another point. Don’t the majority in this case find for R on the ground that the events were unforeseeable? Don’t they say that, though it may have been foreseeable that an adult would have stolen the car it would not be foreseeable, or there
wasn’t sufficient evidence to conclude that it was foreseeable, that a minor would steal the car? And that a minor would take the car for a joyride? Isn’t this odd? As Jason says, this seems rather otherworldly. Kids do this all the time. It is one of the
significant problems of modern policing. It seems that this was even more true of the area in which these events took place. Can we agree that, even if we approve of the result in the case, we cannot accept the reasoning of the majority? Perhaps I am being
unfair, but it seems to me that the majority have either lost touch with a reality of modern life or are just not telling the truth. I suspect the latter. Should we really be comfortable with this, as long as we get the result we are after?
Another thing: I am struck by the fact that at least many of the Canadian contributors to this discussion have argued along the following lines. “The law in Canada says x, y and z. According to x, y and z, the result should have been r. The majority got to
not-r by doing something illegitimate.” Some commentators, I am thinking especially of Lewis, have even disclaimed any personal commitment to r. They just think that r is what the law in Canada requires. Am I being unfair when I say that one line of response
to this has been to say something that could be paraphrased as “Well who cares about that? Just get the right result.” I don’t detect much legal analysis in these replies (I assume that citation of case law, especially the case law of a foreign jurisdiction,
is not itself legal analysis). But isn’t this something that we should care about?
It might also be worth while to identify precisely why you think that J should not be able to recover (if that is what you do think). Is it because J broke the law in stealing the car. If so, then isn’t this intuition best reflected in the illegality defence
rather than in the way that it was reflected in this case? Shouldn’t we then say that the majority were wrong, though they got right result rather than just siding with them? My own view is that this “J is an outlaw” response to the case is likely to explain
much of the antipathy to J recovering, but for reasons I won’t repeat here my view is that this position is unjustified. Perhaps the intuition, though, is that J should not be able to sue R when J consciously took the risk that materialised in his injury.
This is to say that J was volens – that R created a risk but that J voluntarily ‘took on’ that same risk when deciding to steal a car from R. Whether you think that will depend on what you make of his age, etc. Again, though, this doesn’t really support the
majority. Perhaps you think that C (or J himself) was so much more responsible for J’s injury than R was that R should not have to pay damages at all; in which case in principle this could be reflected properly in the contribution (or contributory negligence)
rules, at least if they (as I see it) were approached more rationally than they are at present. Again, this is not the majority’s view. If you are against J here for a different reason, I’d be interested to hear what it might be.
And one last thing: It might be worth reflecting on the kind of disagreement that we are seeing here. We have distinguished commentators on the law unable to agree on pretty basic questions such as whether this was an entirely ordinary kind of case or whether
it raised exceptional issues. Some say that finding liability would involve an outrageous extension of the law of negligence. Others say (including the dissenters) that it would involve no extension at all. My own view is that the cases that impose rules that
restrict recover are (to my mind) pretty clearly cutting back on liability rather than failing to extend it. Some think that there should be liability in this case. Others that it is ‘obvious’ that there should not; that this is even a simple and clear case
in which anyone could see that there should be no liability. No doubt about it.
My question is: What are we actually arguing about here? Anything at all? If scholars who have dedicated themselves to the study of this area of the law can be so divided on these really rather basic questions, perhaps we have to admit that – at least if we
are talking about today’s positive law of negligence – the law has become so empty that almost anything can be said about it. If the law’s job is to guide practical reason, then this area of the law seems to be on strike.
Just to clarify, I am not saying that the moral question raised in the case was an easy one. I would say that it is a difficult one as it tests the boundaries of our conceptions of responsibility, but that matter is separate. It might be worth reflecting on
the fact that here in NZ (and I imagine elsewhere), there is considerable controversy over high speed police chases that end in kids who have stolen cars being killed. One response to this kind of think is to say “Well, it’s the bloody kids’ fault. Shouldn’t
have stolen the car”. I have to say that I am proud not to belong to that class of thinker. It is also notable that that isn’t the police’s view. They clearly think that they do have an obligation to care for the safety of the joyrider. Quite right too. Also,
there are of course other ways of looking at tort law than focusing on today’s positive ‘law’, but that is another matter too.
All the best
Allan
Jason Neyers
Professor of Law
Faculty of Law
Western University
Law Building Rm 26
t. 519.661.2111 (x88435)